OTHER
VOICES: PAY EQUITY IS UNFAIR TO WOMEN
Comparable
worth sounds great for women, but it would actually reduce their job
opportunities.
Striking secretaries at Yale
recently threatened to bring the 284-year-old university to a standstill over
what they saw as discrimination in wages favoring men over women. Female
workers in Washington State won a discrimination suit in a
federal district court that may cost the state government nearly $1 billion in
back pay and increased wages. The U.S. House of Representatives passed a bill
in the last session of Congress that required all federal jobs to be
reevaluated, with the aim of raising the pay for jobs held mainly by women. All
these actions were taken in the name of comparable worth, a controversial -
theory that jobs have an intrinsic, measurable value that should dictate the
wages paid. Sounds like a great deal for women trapped in underpaid
occupations, doesn't it? In the short run it may be: women in jobs directly
affected by the strikes, suits, and legislation could get higher wages. But in
the long run all women will lose. If the proponents of comparable worth succeed
in their quest, they will bring about the most radical alteration of our
economy in the nation's history, replacing the market system with a system of
administered wages. Why, then, have so many otherwise sensible people endorsed
comparable worth? The answer lies partly in the ability of comparable worth
advocates to cloak themselves in the rhetoric of
fairness. They have even coined a phrase to describe their goal: pay equity.
Mimicking the strategy of the civil rights movement, they point to the
statistical disparity between the average earnings of men and women and
conclude that discrimination must exist. They note the high concentration of
women in certain occupations and claim job segregation. But equal pay for equal
work is the law of the land, as is the guarantee that any woman has the right
to any job for which she is qualified. What pay equity requires is not the
fairness of equal opportunity, but something disturbingly different. In recent
years the courts have held that government ought to remedy any disparities in
the success achieved by various groups in society. Courts routinely find, for
example, that discrimination exists when an employer's work force has fewer
blacks in it than their proportion in the local labor market. With people
conditioned to think this way, comparable worth advocates have only to prove
that women earn less than men to convince many that discrimination is the
cause. The fact that women earn 72 cents for every dollar that men earn, based
on their average hourly wages, leads few people to ask why. Instead, they ask
what we can do about it. The wage gap between men and women is a complex
phenomenon. No single explanation suffices. Women continue to work at different
jobs than men, with fully half of all women concentrated in three occupations
despite strides in opening up positions that have been male enclaves. These
female occupations --sales, clerical, and professional--command salaries in the
market commensurate with the supply and demand of people able and willing to
perform the work. Earnings clearly play only a partial role in women's decision
to work in a < limited number of jobs. Of far greater importance is the need
that most women have to balance the demands of a job with the responsibilities
of family life. Working mothers may be willing to take less pay to get other
benefits--a job that doesn't penalize the woman who intermittently interrupts
her career for childbearing, or a job that provides regular working hours and
proximity to a telephone in case of a child-related emergency. Comparable worth
advocates want no part of such complexities. It is as if they cannot conceive
that women are capable of acting in their self-interest. Instead, they depict
working women as victims of conspiracy and oppression, incapable of making
rational decisions about their needs and desires. The fact that women continue
to seek employment primarily in low-paying, female- dominated jobs despite
expanded opportunity in higher-paying, traditionally male occupations does not
suggest to comparable worth advocates that the non- monetary benefits of
certain jobs may have appeal. Rather, it suggests to them that women need
protection from the consequences of their choices. While espousing feminist
ideology, the comparable worth advocates offer up protectionist legislation to
insulate women from the demands of the market. But like so much of what passes
for protection, comparable worth may make victims of its intended
beneficiaries. Women will ultimately be the biggest losers. IF COMPARABLE WORTH
becomes the law of the land, higher salaries almost certainly will mean fewer
jobs in traditionally female occupations. Employers forced to pay higher wages
with no concomitant rise in productivity have to raise prices or reduce the
number of jobs. What manager, faced with a decision between losing his
competitive edge by hiking prices or making do with
fewer secretaries, will choose the former, particularly in the age of computers
and word processors? Australia has had a variation of comparable
worth in both the public and private sectors since 1972. Within five years of
enactment of its law, female unemployment in Australia rose, the number of women working
part time increased, and the growth of female participation in the labor force
slowed. What the comparable worth advocates always ignore is who will bear the
costs of the pay increases their system would mandate. The costs will not be
borne by some elite band of larcenous employers. They will be borne mainly by
women.
LINDA
CHAVEZ, OTHER VOICES: PAY EQUITY IS
UNFAIR TO WOMEN Comparable worth sounds great for women, but it would actually
reduce their job opportunities..
, Fortune, 03-04-1985, pp 161.
eLibrary is a service of Tucows, Inc. Copyright ©
2002. All rights reserved.